René Descartes, the seventeenth century French philosopher considered by many to be one of the founders of modern European rationalism, was troubled by doubt. What if, he wondered, everything that I see, hear and touch is not fundamentally, really real? What if everything I know, or think I know is false and even the truths of mathematics and physics, which seem entirely unshakeable, are clever lies and not universal laws? Descartes confronts his doubt in a book he called Meditations on First Philosophy, composed in 1640. At the beginning of the First Meditation, Descartes lays out his program:
Some years ago I was struck by the large number of falsehoods that I had accepted as true in my childhood, and by the highly doubtful nature of the whole edifice that I had subsequently based on them. I realized that it was necessary, once in the course of my life, to demolish everything completely and start again right from the foundations if I wanted to establish anything at all in the sciences that was stable and likely to last.
Descartes begins his demolition work by acknowledging the ways in which the senses can be deceived while awake and the impossible visions that come to people when they sleep. However, even if one’s perception can be called into doubt in these particular circumstances, the fundamental truths of the universe—meaning arithmetic, geometry, the laws of physics and the like—would still hold. Even while asleep and dreaming, Decartes writes, two plus three makes five, never four or six.
However, the meditation goes further. For who is to say if these laws, the world, the sky and the sun, the whole universe, do not really exist but that it is God who makes them appear to exist? How can one know for certain that God himself does not contrive things so that one goes wrong every time one adds two and three? God’s good nature renders unlikely this kind of malicious trickery and makes Decartes’ doubts themselves doubtful. In order to reach his desired state of radical doubt, in which he can call into question everything he accepted, by habit, to be reality, Descartes makes use of a convenient fiction:
I will suppose therefore that not God, who is supremely good and the source of truth, but rather some evil demon (sed genium aliquem malignum) of the utmost power and cunning has employed all his energies in order to deceive me. I shall think that the sky, the air, the earth, colors, shapes, sounds and all external things are merely the delusions of dreams which he has devised to ensnare my judgement. I shall consider myself as not having hands or eyes, flesh or blood or senses, but as falsely believing that I have all these things. I shall stubbornly and firmly persist in this meditation; and, even if it is not in my power to know the truth, I shall at least do what is in my power, that is, resolutely guard against assenting to any falsehoods, so that the deceiver, however powerful and cunning he may be, will be unable to impose on me in the slightest degree.
From this position of radical doubt, in which he presumes that an evil force has directed all his energies merely in order to trick him, Descartes ultimately arrives at bedrock that he knows must be true. This is the famous dictum cogito, ergo sum, I think therefore I am. Whatever else happens, even if all his thoughts are false delusions, the fact that he is thinking cannot itself be wrong. The evil demon is directing his energies at deceiving something and that something is him, Descartes. The thought I exist can, therefore, never be false, however much the demon applies his energies.
What interests us here, though, is not the rationalist method Decartes builds from that moment of radical doubt. To a Zoroastrian ear, the notion of an evil demon has a familiar ring. Is Decartes not, somehow, reflecting the belief in the existence of the evil spirit, whose existence is entirely opposed to the good and who corrupts the world and deludes people’s beliefs and senses? The parallel is not entirely accurate of course: Descartes’ evil demon is more reminiscent of the gnostic demiurge, that evil being who created the world solely in order to torment human beings, while the good, true God stands outside and beyond the world. In the Zoroastrian conception, the world itself is inherently good, it exists (as do we) and our perception of it is to be trusted. The evil spirit corrupted the world in his attack on it, evil and good have become mixed but the tradition does not embrace an ontologically dualist vision of the world itself and humans’ mortal lives as inherently delusions.
Nevertheless, doubt is linked with the evil spirit in the Zoroastrian tradition. Doubt is not only the result of the meddling of the evil spirit but the cause of the revelation of his existence. As in Descartes’ Meditations, doubt is productive. In my previous post I mentioned the role that doubt plays in launching the theological quest in the Shkand Gumanig Wizar and the Dadestan i Menog i Xrad. However, doubt plays this role in the Gathas as well. We can take, for example, the opening section of Yasna 29. In the first stanza of the poem, the soul of the Cow complains to Ahura Mazda (in Martin Schwartz‘s translation in his article “Gathic Compositional History, Y 29, and Bovine Symbolism):
To you the Cow’s soul complained: “For whom
did You shape me? Who fashioned me? Fury
with force, violence with brazen vice have gripped
me with might; I have no pastor other than You,
so appear to me with good pastur(ag)e.”
The soul of the Cow, that ideal manifestation of bovinity in the heavenly sphere, is troubled by violence and without a protector. In its pain, the soul of the Cow calls out for aid. This plea is repeated by the members of the divine panoply: the Fashioner of the Cow asks Rightness (Asha) who he will appoint as the lord and protector of the Cow. The Fashioner of the Cow replies that no champion is to be found (29:3): “there is no liberator, free of malice, on behalf of the Cow.”
Only Lord Wisdom (Ahura Mazda) can provide a protector. In stanza five, the Soul of the Cow and the soul of Zarathushtra himself are described as standing with hands outstretched in supplication, asking:
“Is there no
hope for the right-living person, none for the
cattleman surrounded by wrongful ones?”
Ahura Mazda’s answer is, it seems at first, negative: no hope has been found in the world, no judgement in accord with Rightness. But in next stanza Lord Widsom asks his own question. Having created the “mantra of poured butter and milk for the Cow,” he asks Good Mind (Vohu Mana) if he has found someone who can deliver this beneficent mantra to mortals on earth. Vohu Mana replies that indeed he has; as 29:8 reveals, the revealer of the mantra is none other than Spitama Zarathushtra himself.
But the Soul of the Cow is unsatisfied. Is this the champion he pleaded for?
“I who have
(thus) gotten (on my behalf merely) the mightless
voice of a powerless man instead, (I) who wish
for someone who is dominant with might! When
will there ever be someone to give him help of hands?”
In the final stanza, the poet answers this lament. Zarathushtra’s hands are helped by the divine triad of Rightness, Good Mind and Lord Wisdom. Through his revelation, the Prophet aids mortals, including the long-suffering cows, more than any herculean strong man. “Take account of me,” he says to them, “come down to us here.” It is Zarathushtra’s ability to channel and call upon the divine that settles the Soul of the Cow’s complaint.
There are two species of doubt in Yasna 29. The first is the doubt exhibited by the Soul of the Cow. We might call this kind of doubt existential: it is closer to worry or anxiety, doubt about the safety of cows and pasturage, about protection against marauding raiders. This is of a different order than Decartes’ posulation of the evil demon. The Soul of the Cow’s doubt is existential while Descartes is epistemological: he doubts not his own life and safety but his perception and understanding of the world.
What of Zarathushtra’s doubt? When Zarathushtra portrays his spiritual self as standing with his hands outstretched beside the Soul of the Cow, he does not ask Ahura Mazda for his own protection. Zarathushtra’s question is one with deep ethical implications: can there be justice? Is there no recourse for wrongdoing? The poet’s doubt is global, addressing the foundation of the order of the universe. It is to his doubt that Ahura Mazda responds – and the Soul of the Cow expresses its dissatisfaction – granting Zarathushtra his ritual and poetic mission. Like Descartes, Zarathushtra’s doubt is the catalyst for revelation.
One Reply to “Doubt: Descartes and the Gathas”
Comments are closed.